Saturday, September 24, 2016

Thinking about Jesus: Report from a Work in Progress

This piece was originally published in the Cabrini Communicator.


When I started college, I ran into three kinds of people who talked to me about Jesus. One was David White, a Quaker with strong interests in Asian philosophy. He had done serious work on Indian systems of thought and mental discipline. He seemed to have a broad understanding of  what human life was about, what to do next, how to be unobviously good – rooted in old and converging traditions from three continents. His comment about Jesus: “Whatever he is, he is not a philosopher.”

A second influence came from a couple of competent New Testament scholars, who taught me what it is to be careful in interpreting a text. They made it clear that the New Testament scholarship enterprise was one honking beautiful thing, in which the research tools were well developed, the questions refined and processed by lots of very good minds. It seemed to me unlikely that I would, very soon, be able to make any contribution to this enterprise, and it seemed likely that a lifework would result in a footnote to a footnote somewhere.

The third influence came from some folks I might never have met, except that they seemed to be the only people around not mostly into sex, drugs, and rock and roll – none of which I was ready for, my freshman year at Macalester. This was the Inter-Varsity Christian Fellowship, an evangelical group that put weight on a personal relationship with Jesus initiated in a moment of conversion, fueled by feelings derived heavily from Bob Dylan and Leonard Cohen. Their message was that an intimate understanding of Jesus was: (1) what I needed; (2) all I needed; and (3) pretty easy to get, if I just wanted it enough.

This was the Protestant counterpart to what I had run into from Catholicism in my youth: the idea that there was some well understood way to salvation enshrined in the Vatican, passed out through mysterious spiritual and educational conduits to priests and nuns, and available in limited quantities to the spiritually dense people in the pews, who will do fine, the way pets do fine, if they were obedient, keep themselves clean, remember their place, and take in as much water as their little water glasses can hold.

These messages all converged to say: “Whatever you do, don’t think about Jesus.” The evangelicals said that the whole truth was simple, and not to be found by thinking. My home-town Catholics said the whole truth was complicated, secured in the monopoly pockets of semi-Martians, in the various holy orders. The historians said it was complicated, and that, to the extent it could be covered, they had it covered. And my old friend David White said that, whatever was there, it wasn’t interesting in the way philosophers were interesting – not a line of thought to be retraced.

The Catholic liberals I met later didn’t dispute the consensus. They understood Jesus as a mid-point in a line of anti-oppression prophets culminating in Karl Marx: the point is not to understand the world but to change it.  Jesus’ message is simple, has to be simple, as a foundation for simple people’s action against oppression.

Recently, I have had a chance to think a few hours a day, and I find myself wanting to think about Jesus, even though, for these various reasons, I’m not supposed to. It started out with noticing something. Dominic Crossan and his colleagues in the Jesus Seminar have emphasized that, with the sayings and stories of Jesus, there is usually good reason to believe that the moral was added later, that the oldest bit is a story or observation without much commentary. Looking over the list of these stripped down sayings and stories, I was struck with their similarity to remarks of early philosophers from whom we also have fragments and stories, without significant context. In particular, his stuff reminded me a lot of  Heraclitus, of Marcus Aurelius, and of the collection of paradoxes that constitutes the skeptical manuals of Sextus Empiricus.

Heraclitus is best known for a couple of sayings: ‘You can’t step in the same river twice,’ and ‘The upward and the downward way are one.’ These sayings are typically philosophical, so it is perhaps useful to look closely at them. The first says that something which we generally take as simple and uncontroversial is in fact plausibly seen as multiple and complex: as KFAI is a different station every hour, the Mississippi is a different river every second. New stuff comes in; old stuff goes out. What we call a thing is really a flow, a movement, an action. (Heracleitus thought about candle flames the same way.) Obviously, once one has grasped this fact, the questions press in: ‘How much other stuff that we think of as one is really also many?,’ and ‘Does it make some important difference if we start noticing the manyness in onenesses?’

The other remark goes in the opposite direction. Anybody who has ever pedaled a bike up to the youth hostel at the top of the hill in the evening, then glided down in the morning, can testify that the upward and the downward way are as different as any two things in human experience. Yet, we know, it’s the same road, the same stones, exactly. Two things that we take to be different can be reasonably seen as the same. Again, this presses the questions, ‘What else is like this?’ and ‘Does this singleness in doubleness matter?’

Philosophers love this kind of thing. They collect paradoxes and double-meanings and mistakes the way bug collectors collect bugs. For philosophers, this is a really intense and fairly autonomous interest. It doesn’t necessarily have to go anyplace or mean anything. More practical people want to know: what use is this? Can I make it part of my speech to my kids about why not to do drugs or to the sales team about approaching difficult clients, or can I incorporate it into a letter to the editor on the deceptive slowness of climate change? Where’s the sermon? Where’s the pep talk? Where’s the point? But philosophers find puzzles to be fun and revealing for their own sake, and they are slow to make messages out of them. They want to understand, or at least appreciate, human beings’ relationship to the world, what happens when people try to know the world or name the world, the exact ways that reality keeps slipping out of our grasp.

Some of what Jesus says fits Heracleitus’ models. The seeds all go to the same place; the seeds go to very different places.  The old woman gave the temple much less than the rich man gave; both gave huge amounts. Other sayings challenge  the common sense reading of a situation. The place next to the host is the best place at the banquet, is the worst place at the banquet (depending on what happens next). It is smart to build new barns after a good harvest; it is stupid to waste time building new barns, whatever the harvest.  One can bring most of the sayings of Jesus into some family of paradox and puzzle, casting them as some kind of warning that one’s initial way of thinking is not the only way of thinking, that human and natural reality resist our categories, play games with our intuitions, will not stay still.

Of course, in the editorial context of the gospels, all of these sayings get a moral point, and those points are generally what anyone sane would call: good advice. But how do we understand their earliest context? Do we really want to understand Jesus as the sort of person who was always moralizing, always admonishing, always on some kind of personal quest for justice? He might have been that way. We know good people who are that way. But it is also imaginable that lots of the stories we read as moral parables might have been originally introduced this way: “Isn’t it strange that…?” or “I just noticed that…” or “Doesn’t it bother anybody that…?” Maybe the philosophy comes first, and the heart follows.

We know that mathematical and philosophic prodigies (essentially, people obsessed with understanding relationships and structures) spring up in the strangest places, sometimes make enormous progress very early in their lives. Jesus might have been one of those.

Such a reading would not upend theology. It would shift our understanding of certain sayings and stories, interacting with every other line of thought we have available about the gospels.

I want to continue trying to work out this idea of Jesus as philosopher. I think it might have something to it. It matters to me because I am a philosopher, and it would be helpful to me to have that as a point of contact with Jesus. The more important point is that any of our experiences of ways of being human is relevant to our reading of sacred texts. People are complicated, and understanding any person is a matter of seeing many layers interacting. It is a life-long pursuit.

We can’t let ourselves get sucked into the idea that the story has to be simple, because we need answers, now, immediately, about everything important. To that, the universe says, “You’ve got to be kidding.”


Wednesday, September 21, 2016

On Reading the Parables of Jesus


A Progress Report: On Reading the Parables of Jesus

If I were picking up the Bible and reading around in the summer parables - the prodigal son, the unjust steward, the good Samaritan, the wedding feast, the narrow gate – I would likely make some connections to my life and then think about them for a while, take it away to my den like found bones. So, for example, I read about the farmer who hatches a plan to secure his future by building new barns for a large harvest. He is surprised when he dies before the barns are finished. Reading that, I say: ‘Yes, I am always looking ahead, making plans on the assumption of extra life. Clearly, if I knew I was going to die soon, lots of that activity would seem pointless, and I would do other things: visit my friends, spend time with my dog.’ The story of the farmer who builds new barns reminds me of a way of thinking that is very familiar to me, the grab for security and safety. It makes me look at my own first impulse in a critical way. (I might go home and pet the dog.)

Reading the gospels in Word Team is different from reading them by myself. The Word Team gets so many meanings out of the text. We go around in a circle, giving our first responses; usually, every person has something different. This information about how the story will be heard is very useful for preaching; one gets a feel for the possible mindsets of this audience. One’s question as a preacher is: how do I say something helpful to people who begin with all these interpretations, making all these connections to issues in their lives?

Stepping back from the process, remembering how it goes, week after week, I want to ask, “So, what is the real point of any particular story?” The story may provoke various thoughts, even obviously helpful and new thoughts, but are they anywhere near to what Jesus had in mind?

In some moods, I dismiss this question. The parables provoke thought. Thought is good. End of story.

But wouldn’t it be a shame if I missed the point?

So I think about what limits can be put on readings, how to winnow down the mass of possible ways of thinking. One might look at the moral as stated in the passage. Usually, after Jesus tells a story, he goes on to explain it to the disciples, or he draws the moral from it. This stuff is often taken by scholars to be later than the parable itself – an attempt by editors to apply the tradition they have received to the needs of a particular community. (The work of the Jesus Seminar is very important in separating the layers of additions from the basic texts.) This commentary is not trivial material. It articulates one community’s experience, a point that some community has found valuable. It is at least a starting point for understanding the text. But any explicit moral is usually just one more interpretation - not authoritative advice on how to read the story.

One might try to use historical scholarship to limit meanings. One knows that the First Century was different from the Twenty First Century, that thoughts are available to us now that would have been just impossible then, and also that the First Century had family structures, economic realities, community relationships assumed as background that we would find very strange. So, one has some hope that one can eliminate readings that rest on realities of our time and search out readings that would have been natural in Jesus’ time.

This is important work. It has limits. History at a distance of two thousand years can identify, from sketchy evidence, general patterns of life. We know, however, that such an account, in our own time, would miss many variations on themes and exceptions to rules.  Historians in the future may know what laws were on the books but not necessarily how they were applied or enforced. They may get pictures of the ideal family, the normative career, the People Magazine version of success, but not necessarily a sense of the compromises and resignations and creative adaptations that intelligent people made to those ideals and norms and versions. If one becomes conscious of what an historian even two hundred years from now would miss about our own lives and time, the texture that doesn’t get captured in documents and pronouncements, one gets a sense of the limits of historical context reading as a guide to scriptural interpretation.

This general worry about history is complicated by the fact that Jesus lived at a cultural crossroads, at a time of social change. We might be inclined to think of his teachings as arising in a sleepy village, from the experiences of a simple carpenter, but the sleepy village is a mile away from a large, energetic Roman city, Sepphoris, with huge building projects that might well have lured craftsmen from the whole region. In such a city, one might encounter an astonishing range of teachings and life experiences – including Greek philosophic teachings.

Then there is the problem of genius. Ask a music historian what kind of music a composer born in 1756 might have produced, and the historian will be able to say a lot with certainty, based on what such a person would have heard, what lines of development were emerging, what sorts of patronage were available in the late 18th Century. But the historian could not predict Mozart, could not predict what a mind fixed constantly on music from early childhood might come up with. So, if we think of Jesus as a person obsessed with certain relationships and problems from very early on, working something out steadily over time, we have to admit that the things he could have come up with may not be well explained by his context.

Is theology relevant? Some people in the early church understood Jesus to be a cosmic principle, equal to God, the sole mediator between humanity and God. Does the question, “What would a person with that status say?” give us any help in reading the gospels? I can’t see how it could. If Jesus was very different from other human beings, as a god among mortals is different, that just eliminates any possible platform for interpretation. We can’t say how a mind like that might think. So my working hypothesis is that, if this grand picture of the ultimate significance of Jesus has truth to it, whatever Jesus became arose out of an understandable human experience. It is not impossible that the meaning of a life might be larger than the person living it can understand. But, so far as I can see, if one attributes god-like consciousness to the author of the parables, one simply gives up on the project of discovering what they meant. Any “good” reading is as likely as any other. One might be forced to come to this conclusion, at the end of the day, but it is a shame to give up too early on the idea that these stories might teach us something radically new, if we pay the right kind of attention.

How do we proceed?

One way I begin is to look for a minimal content to the stories, a set of ideas that come up over and over and that might be the basic insight, out of which various applications arise. I want to ask: what did Jesus tend to notice and think about? He tells a lot of stories, for example, that show how different perspectives change one’s way of seeing. A coin in the box of ten is just one tenth of one’s wealth. But a lost coin becomes an obsession. One thinks about it to the exclusion of everything else. Building a new barn seems like a great idea when one is healthy and looking forward to many years of prosperity. If one learns one is going to die very soon, it suddenly seems like a totally crazy project. The steward who is fired from his job comes to view business practices that would have seemed bizarre to him the day before the firing as just the right way to secure his future. If one pauses to consider what this structure means before rushing on to the next, moral thought, one is left with a general attitude toward life: whatever you value or pursue or take to be obvious, there’s likely a perspective from which that is not valuable, not a good project, obviously false.  One can imagine Jesus observing rigid commitments and noticing that they can be dissolved by a simple shift in perspective.

I suspect that, whatever moral or social-critical direction Jesus’ teaching eventually takes, it begins its life as a cluster of mental habits and approaches, a way of seeing through things.

Here is another possible member of this cluster. Think about that story of the feast where someone sees a place next to the host and runs to grab it. That is a natural move. One wants honor. One goes for the best place. But the natural move, the first thing that occurs to a person, risks disgrace, in certain very likely circumstances: the host is saving that place for a distinguished friend. One can add the moral point: don’t be concerned about honor, practice humility, stuff like that. But, again, if one pauses just before the moral point, there is a general habit of mind evident here: be suspicious of the direct approach, of your first impulse, of what comes naturally. Again, one can imagine Jesus watching people go astray in that way and gathering stories.

Daniel Kahneman, a behavioral economist, talks about two systems of judgment, one very fast and tending to simplify choices, the other much slower but also likelier to get it right. He shows with some very elegant experiments that people are often ruled by a set of decision standards that they would never endorse if they really looked at them. We are animals who once had to make some decisions very quickly, and we carry with us intuitive mechanisms that often don’t serve us very well. So, perhaps like Jesus, Kahneman recommends a habit of mind that tries to get some distance from first impressions and first impulses.

I think about the recommendation that one choose the narrow gate. When one is coming back from the State Fair, after the grandstand show, one is inclined to take the freeway home. One imagines all those lanes, no stoplights, a direct route. One might then pause a minute and reflect that tens of thousands of people are having that same thought and heading in the same direction, and choose instead to take the back road. (See A Beautiful Mind for an economic version of this idea.)

My project over the last couple of years has been to identify a way of thinking and seeing underlying different stories and sayings in the gospels. It seems to me likely that whatever moral and social revolution the gospels contain is somehow founded on a new way of seeing, one that breaks the hold of established conventions and assumptions.

I have been influenced in the last few years by the hopeful story Norman Doidge tells in his books, The Brain that Changes Itself and The Brain’s Way of Healing, both introductions to the science of neuroplasticity - the idea that basic ways of processing experience can be rewired by conscious effort, and that there is a clear direction toward health and human connection that provides a rationale for such rewiring efforts. These books, which remind me of the New Testament in their spirit, raise an important question for me: did Jesus discover a new kind of mind, and was his fundamental teaching – at some point in his career - a recommendation of that mind?

One of our Easter readings, Ezekiel 36, puts these words in the mouth of a very frustrated God, a God at his wit’s end: “I will give you a new heart, and a new spirit I will put within you. And I will remove the heart of stone from your flesh and give you a heart of flesh.” Every year, this reading alarms me. I think of bio-engineering, and of all the projects dictators have undertaken to remake their people into the right sort. Mao and his cultural revolution come to mind.  And yet reform has to be something more than new beliefs, a new enthusiasm. People who are still the old person just keep making their old mistakes in new ways. (The picture of Peter in the gospels makes that point over and over.) Is it possible that Jesus, at some stage in his career, is offering people a set of exercises to build a new mind, out of which new relations and a new society might emerge?

That’s what I’m working on. More later.

Tuesday, May 31, 2016

Some Notes on Ann Sharp's Thinking about Religion


Do  we put what is precious at risk through conversation?

"Do not give dogs what is sacred; do not throw your pearls to pigs. If you do, they may trample them under their feet, and turn and tear you to pieces.” Jesus, in Matthew 7:6, Bible, New International Version.

Both Matthew Lipman and Ann Sharp sometimes write that Philosophy for Children discussions promote religious understanding and growth – understood in quite traditional ways. In 1984, Lipman presents philosophic discussion as a way of  encountering religious stories: “In any educational context, whether religious or otherwise, reasoning and inquiry skills are cultivated in order to improve the ability of students to retrieve meanings from what they read and hear and otherwise perceive in the world about them. Often the curriculum is scripture and commentary; the meanings to be retrieved are religious meanings.” (29)  He gives examples in this article of ways to use particular reasoning skills to understand traditional stories; one senses the influence of the great Jewish interpretive traditions in these remarks.

In a late autobiographical written interview exchange, Ann Sharp reflects on many religious institutions and influences over decades of her early life; clearly, the starting points for her own early journeys of thought were religious stories and  claims. She writes with regret about the theological poverty of contemporary education: “I often wonder if one of the reasons why my undergraduates are so unmotivated toward philosophical thinking is because they don’t have access to theological speculation, and much of what they do have in terms of religious background, if anything, is dogmatic, not subject to personal reflection and divorced from their everyday life.” (34, emphasis mine). (One might take Lipman’s recommendation to be a call for infusing dogmatic religious materials with personal reflections that connect them to everyday life, for the philosophic processing of religious stories to elicit their meanings. ) Later in the interview, Sharp summarizes her current relationship to religious questions: she was once interested in reconciling faith and reason, but has become convinced, through her wider reading of philosophy, that faith and reason were “speaking different languages with regard to human experience.” It is centrally important to understand how this conviction influences Sharp’s attitude toward the religious and spiritual significance of Philosophy for Children.
   
The question about the relevance of philosophy discussions in the classroom to religious stories and assertions was not central in the early days of the Philosophy for Children movement. When Lipman wrote his classroom novels, he avoided many topics that would annoy and frighten religious people. He never has a child say, as innumerable children have said in innumerable elementary schools: ‘You’re a Lutheran, so you are going to hell’ or ‘The teacher is just wrong about dinosaurs, because the world is really only 6000 years old.’ Lipman was concerned to give his basic approach to inquiry a foothold in public schools, and so he has Harry start out thinking about reversible sentences, a matter on which few parents have opinions. Perhaps he hoped that the children would practice their new-found skills on all the claims they were commanded to believe, but he didn’t directly address religious convictions in the early novels.

Lipman’s initial strategy was certainly right. There was no other way to introduce philosophy into the schools. But, apart from strategic considerations, how do we understand the relationship between the community of inquiry and those beliefs that people hold closest: their religious, spiritual, and aesthetic commitments? Is there something special about these beliefs that requires a different approach than is appropriate to, for example, the question about the definition of friendship?
In her writings, Ann Sharp says quite a lot that is relevant to this question. She comes at it from several directions, in papers written for different purposes and audiences over three decades.

Her position is sometimes hard to make out, for several interlocking reasons. She has the generous habit of quoting briefly, in passing, from substantial works, without saying whether she agrees with the quotations or just finds the views provocative, and without locating the quotes within philosophic systems. This is useful as bibliography. She gives the reader some leads for future work on the topic. This is not, however, helpful to someone who is trying to isolate Ann’s own position.

In almost everything she writes on these topics, Ann is attempting to present the basic method of philosophy for children and the rationale for using that method in the public schools. This is also a reasonable and generous impulse: many readers  will need considerable background before they can grasp any particular issue related the program. Further, she feels a natural responsibility to spread the word about this new educational initiative. However, her rehearsal of basic points crowds out new arguments and insights in the articles, and it eats space that could be used for a fuller development of the most central and potentially controversial claims.

Finally, when Sharp writes about the community of inquiry, she describes the ideal case: the classroom in which everything goes right. In such a classroom, students adopt philosophic practices quickly, acquire necessary skills, make space for each other’s contributions, treat each other carefully, and progress from individual conceptual analysis to the construction of a story that takes in all the divergent views represented in their community. The teacher facilitates without dominating, skillfully asking the right question to move the discussion forward. I have worked with these materials in many classrooms, and it is remarkable how often they succeed, how well they work, and how far people can take the conversation, even on the first day. However, it doesn’t always work this way: the practice is good but not supernatural. Sharp’s way of writing obscures the question of risk. I may endanger my connection to a view I care about by exposing it to a community of inquiry. In the ideal case, there might be no risk. But not every community is safe; not every teacher is able to guarantee a safe space.  

In the following discussion, I will sketch four claims about the relationship between practices in the classroom community of inquiry and religious material (stories, assertions, and concepts). I think that Ann Sharp presents each of these in some of her writings.  Some of them make Philosophy for Children out to be more spiritually and religiously important than others. On a scale of increasing radicalness and decreasing modesty, the claims are these:

1.     Religious topics can reasonably be addressed in the community of inquiry; philosophy for children is a possible source of fresh religious thinking;

2.              Classroom dialogue gives content to notions that are important in religious, spiritual and aesthetic contexts, without competing with, or replacing, religious practice;

3.              Classroom philosophical inquiry is itself religious – a kind of community that is a plausible unifying ideal for a democratic society;

4.              The formation of a classroom community of inquiry creates a work of art, subject to the critical categories appropriate to works of art, and offering the kind of satisfaction that a work of art provides.

The first claim, that the classroom community of inquiry can reasonably engage with some religious claims, metaphors, and stories, is, by itself, very modest. The second claim is also modest. It gives the philosophy for children classroom an important role in helping students to understand the vocabulary of religious belief. Both papers are in basic agreement with Lipman’s claim that philosophy for children can support religious practice. Claim three seems to place philosophy for children in direct competition with religious practice, and claim four maps out an alternative way of understanding philosophic inquiry that avoids this suggestion.

In the following sections, I will show in more detail how Sharp develops each of these claims, making some brief critical comments about her views. I will then look more closely at the two pieces presented in this anthology, in an effort to clarify the question: ‘What risk does philosophy for children pose to closely held beliefs?’

Philosophy for children engages critically and creatively with religious materials.

A two-part, 1994 paper, “The Religious Dimension of Philosophy for Children” (Journal of Value Inquiry, March and November 1994), is a plausible starting point for thinking about Ann’s views on religious content in classroom philosophy discussions. Part one presents a basic thesis, with many examples. Religions address “our understanding of what life is all about, its purpose and meaning.” (3) They contain “ideas and beliefs about the essential nature of the world and (one’s) place in it,” (3)  often expressed through metaphors. Feminist theologians have shown what it is like to engage in criticism of such metaphors, arguing that some traditional pictures - of the universe under the control of an all-powerful lawgiver, for example - are inadequate to the experience of some people, especially women, and to some problems faced by humanity, and need to be replaced by other, better metaphors.  

The basic material of religious positions is, in this way, open to criticism; religious
topics can reasonably be addressed in the community of inquiry: “Questions of religious belief would become a subject for collaborative reflection and inquiry connected to the other qualities and moods of their daily experience which fund the changing and complicated stories of our humanness.” (11) Indeed, children have a loose enough relationship to traditional metaphors to come up with viable alternatives that adults might miss.

In part 2, Ann begins by observing that, in international teacher workshops at Mendham, New Jersey, the conversation approaches a new intellectual ideal: transcultural consciousness. “Most individuals operate from a far narrower frame of reference from that of which they are capable, failing to transcend the influence of their particular culture, their particular parents, and their particular childhood experience that has formed their view of the world…. It has been the experience of many of the participants that they do come to understand the world-views of others and take different perspectives into account.” (2)

The remainder of the article reviews in detail the strategies and values of classroom philosophy, looking at how this practice might enable children to go beyond their own upbringing and culture to achieve empathy and to craft new metaphors that respond to current crises. So philosophy for children is positioned as a possible source of fresh religious thinking, crafting metaphors that respond forcefully to the crises of racism, environmental degradation, and all kinds of oppression.

The optimism expressed in these two papers is exhilarating. Events since 1994 have made anyone reasonable hope for new practices that allow people with different basic metaphors to come into relationships of common understanding and mutual appreciation. Events have also made the difficulties clear: faiths are so often understood as irreconcilable opposites, ultimate choices, reasons to go to war. In 1994, Ann was concerned to present the basic idea of philosophy for children to a skeptical world: much of her writing is introductory exposition of basic approaches. What is missing is an appropriately detailed discussion of how one can approach religious material in classroom discussion without trivializing it. People’s commitment to religious metaphors is supported by the experience of their lives, by the examples that hold them up as people. It is not a matter of giving (and countering) simple reasons, and the discussions are not quick. A model that works well for concepts quite distant from the core values and core identities of participants may need revolutionary adaptation to address closely held beliefs that define who these people are. We need more experience and more honest experiments to make good on what Ann promised in 1994.   

Philosophy for children practice exemplifies central concepts used in religious contexts.

In some of her work, Sharp suggests a friendly and complementary way of building bridges between religious practice and the practice of philosophy for children:
classroom dialogue sometimes gives content to notions that are important in religious contexts, without competing with or replacing religious practice. The classroom can become one more field of action in which religious concepts are rediscovered and put into practice: “The enterprise comes to be characterized by hope – hope that the dialogue itself will enable participants to transcend their diverse perspectives without sacrificing the richness and the uniqueness of each of the world-views shared. Participants seem to be willing to work together, to work creatively with rules, and to consciously create an ambiance of trust, openness, and wonder. A certain quality of agape or love seems to develop with time.” (, “The Aesthetic Dimension of the Community of Inquiry,” (Inquiry: Critical Thinking Across the Disciplines, Autumn 1997)73)  

In “The Community of Inquiry as Ritual Participation” (in Children Philosophize Worldwide, Frankfurt, 2009), Sharp uses the notion of ritual, understood in a Confucian way, to explain the framework within which classroom philosophy sessions proceed. One can take this as a suggestion about how a notion that has its usual home in religious contexts is enlivened and exercised by other uses.

Philosophy for children is a particular form of religious activity.

In some of her writing, Sharp goes beyond recognizing common features in religious and philosophical practice to claim philosophic discussions as sacred space (“The Sacred-As-Relationship in the Community of Inquiry” in Philosophy on Top of the World (proceedings of a conference in Iceland in 1997): “John Dewey made a very suggestive remark in his work A Common Faith that each time a community gets together to engage in deliberation, active inquiry into matters of importance, they are engaging in a ritual, a ritual that celebrates the ideals of goodness, truth, and beauty. These ideals do not exist somewhere in another world but are human projections that regulate our inquiry and motivate us to move the actual (that which is) to what we think “ought to be,” a world in which the ideals are incarnate.  This movement towards the ideal is God, or, better yet, what Mary Daly calls “godding.” (9) She quotes with admiration Eva, a Brazilian student, “Couldn’t God also be a relationship? I mean, perhaps it is like friendship. Once you have a friendship, you act very differently and the world even looks different.” This direction, naming the working philosophy classroom as sacred space, as a manifestation of God, is one that clearly appeals to Sharp as a way of re-animating religious practice in an American context.

This line of thought complicates any discussion of the relationship between philosophy for children and religious content. There is, in the 1994 Religious Dimension paper, a fairly clear line on how to understand this relationship: religious claims are metaphors that make broad sense of human beings’ place in the world. They can be criticized for adequacy, as any metaphor can be criticized, within the normal practices of classroom philosophy. This new article suggests that philosophy for children itself embodies a religious metaphor, an ideal of human life, an experience of the sacred – one that could be, in principle, in conflict with other such metaphors. This was surely the kind of scandal that Lipman was so careful to avoid giving in his choice of material for the novels and in his early presentation of the program. Sharp’s attraction to this way of understanding philosophic practice opens a very important (and somewhat dangerous) line of inquiry for the philosophy for children movement, as that movement approaches religiously committed parents and communities as a possible component of their children’s education. Lipman had a clear answer to the question, “Is this program just religious instruction by another name?”  -- something like, “No, this is a collection of generally respected skills that have been found useful in inquiry over 2500 years.”  Sharp’s remarks in the Deweyan direction require a much more complex treatment of that question.

This idea of the place of philosophy for children is most powerfully expressed in the posthumously published paper, “In the Beginning Was the Deed: Empowering Children’s Spiritual Consciousness.” There, Sharp argues that philosophy for children presents children who can no longer believe in God with an alternative point of access to values which have long been honored in religious myth and practice: “Dispensing with God does not have to mean dispensing with spirituality.”

The classroom community of inquiry is a living work of art.

The paper, “The Aesthetic Dimension of the Community of Inquiry,” gives some insight into Sharp’s thinking on questions of aesthetics. Her approach is striking. She doesn’t write about the ways in which one might address aesthetic claims in a philosophy discussion – the community of inquiry taking on the view that the Mona Lisa is a great painting or that Warhol’s soup cans aren’t art. Rather, she discusses the formation of the discussion as creating a work of art, subject to the critical categories appropriate to works of art, and offering the kind of satisfaction that a work of art provides: “The community of inquiry, at its best, offers an immersion in aesthetic experience that can serve as a funded experience in envisioning new possibilities and in making decisions. The sensitivity, the appreciative discerning of parts and wholes, the imaginative manipulation of elements to construct something of harmony and vision, will be dependent on the consciousness and quality of this immersion.” (68) Later, she gives an example of how this aesthetic understanding and aesthetically sensitive construction might manifest themselves in discussion: “If we attend carefully we can observe that the reasoning that takes place in such a group is a narrative exploration that is guided by the principle of continuity. Not only is there continuity between the remarks but there is an effort to actively construct some continuity among views. This group work necessitates a certain de-centering from the ego and a simultaneous focusing on the inquiry itself. One finds that each participant builds on the ideas of others and some participants begin to envision new possibilities for solutions of problems under discussion. A dramatic rehearsal seems to be taking place in which each of the students is imaginatively trying out solutions and testing their consequences with participants of the group. Imaginative empathy grows as the dialogue attempts to bring different perspectives into some kind of balance or harmony. Reading faces becomes as important as attending to words.” 72-3 For Ann, aesthetic values are enacted as well as discussed in philosophy discussions; they describe the form within which a satisfying discussion proceeds.

Sharp also uses aesthetic language to explain the ultimate goal of moral education in the 1983 article, “Education: A Philosophical Journey (Studies in Formative Spirituality, November 1983). After arguing for extensive skill building though reasoned discussion, as a pre-requisite for mature moral life, she describes the desired result: “Ultimately, a moral education should render children capable of thinking for themselves in a way that constitutes a harmonious whole. One’s actions should be right aesthetically as well as morally. Happiness then is the reward of right action, a reward that is intrinsic to itself. People do not do the right thing for praise or some other reward. They act in a certain way, as Wittgenstein says,  because it  fits who they are and is consistent with their own values.” 361 For Sharp, one language for explaining the ideals of classroom discussion and of life-building through philosophic education is language usually applied to works of art: the formation of rich and harmonious wholes.   

Ann Sharp finds a power in philosophic discussion with children that reminds her of what she valued in her long engagement with Christian practice, as a devout child trying to be good, and as an undergraduate in a series of religious schools, teaching in other religious religious schools. As she admits in her autobiographical interview, she came to see philosophy  and religion as different languages. Her professional and personal energy were firmly committed to philosophy, and her feminist and environmental reflections made her aware of the limits of religious images and institutions as inspiration for needed social change. When she writes that secular human  beings are unable to believe in the old manner, to take the idea of a transcendent God seriously, it seems likely that she is also reflecting on her own distance from the faith of her youth and adolescence.

In Sharp’s writing on religious topics, she says various things. Some of her writing is very much in the spirit of Matthew Lipman’s 1984 paper emphasising the value of philosophic training for getting at the meanings of religious texts. To go beyond dogma and blind faith to a living relation with the tradition, to bring religion into dialogue with everyday life, one must do just the kind of alert, critical work that philosophy for children teaches and encourages. Further, to come to some understanding of religious ideals of intimate community and  intense engagement with the world, one needs experience with all manner of serious attempts to live well and thoughtfully, and philosophic engagement can provide such experience. So, in much of what Sharp writes, philosophy for children is positioned as a valuable complement to religious practice, as it was imagined to be complementary by those medieval thinkers that Sharp so much admired.  

In other writings, drawing on Dewey, Sharp explores the idea that philosophic practice can fill the role of religious practice, that the classroom can become sacred space. I think this writing has to be read partly in a personal way, as reflecting Sharp’s increasing distance from the piety of her early years. She is looking for a spiritual home, for a replacement for what she has lost, and philosophy for children is a promising candidate. Beyond that, she is seeking some way to give those for whom “God is dead,” to whom traditional religious practice is no longer relevant, some way of being spiritual - accessing those conceptions, practices, and experiences that have been central to Sharp’s formation. Again, philosophy for children seems a promising direction to explore. It solves both a personal and a societal problem.

One might think, encountering Sharp’s most enthusiastic recommendations of the philosophy classroom as sacred space, that she is recommending a new religion that must be in competition with other religious practice. I think that would be a mistake: she, like Lipman, recommends a family of practices that have the power to enliven children’s thinking about aspects of their religious traditions that are often cold and dead for them, to make the claims of religion interesting and relevant. Sharp’s philosophic training did her that service, and she is passing on what she has learned. That she came to assign to philosophic practice a supreme importance, and to withdraw from the traditions that she once embraced, is important in her biography, but it is not central to understanding how philosophy may be of use in religious education.

One must also remember the tentativeness and playfulness of these essays. Sharp is trying out various ways of understanding what happens in the philosophy classroom. It is natural to think of the ideal classroom discussion as embodying something like agape, the highest kind of love and respect. It is also natural to imagine the classroom as a performative space where a powerful work of art comes into being through the independent contributions of many people. There are perhaps other good metaphors. It would run totally counter to Sharp’s deepest commitments to take any metaphor as absolute or exclusive.
I see the problem of risk, the problem of fundamental opposition between philosophic practice in the classroom and the reality of some religious faith, in other directions. The problem is not that philosophy is some kind of competing religion. It might be that, for some people, but it need not be. The problem is that basic features of philosophic practice may leave no space for serious religious talk. In the second part of this introduction, I want to give space to that worry.

How Religious Commitments Enter into Classroom Discussion   

In the paper, “Is There an Essence to Education?” (Journal of Moral Education, October 1986, reprinted here), Sharp defends the claim that it is at least a necessary condition for education, and perhaps its essence, that “children become conscious of themselves in relationship to the other people in their world.” Such consciousness requires  imaginative engagement with other people’s views and the testing of possibilities within a classroom community of inquiry. She describes a conversation about friendship in which children propose several promising accounts, construct counter-examples to each account, and decide, at the end, to leave all the accounts on the board as part of the meaning of friendship, while acknowledging that none of them is without problems. They feel at the end that they have made progress: thinking of these accounts and finding difficulties with them.  The discussion is a fine example of what happens in a good, long-enough philosophy for children session.

I agree with Sharp  that the discussion she describes is valuable and that it makes an important contribution to the education of the children. It is, however, a particular conversation, in two ways. The topic is friendship, a relationship that most of the students have experienced and observed in many forms. They will have no trouble evaluating the claims or the counter-examples from their own experience, from the experience of their friends, or from easily imagined variants of stories with which they are familiar. And friendship is a public topic: it is only possible because people have some broad agreement about what it is. This group’s very permissive account is not just interesting conceptual work; it also affirms the possibility of a variety of relationships that matter to people. The discussion makes the world safe for many kinds of friendship. It is almost an agreement: we will allow this sort of exception to our general expectations.

So, there seems to be no problem with the claim that education regarding friendship happens in the way described. I have some worries about the generalization of that claim: “It is a mistake to think that there is a necessary dichotomy between the development of individual identity, individual thoughts, individual styles, and the  community of inquiry. On the contrary, it is through the community of inquiry that children come to express their views, develop their own ideas about the world and share an experience in which they are accepted by others.”(192) What about the situation in which a child’s experience is far enough removed from that of others that they have no way of sharing that experience briefly in a community of inquiry discussion? Consider for example the child who is a devout Baptist because his aunt is a devout Baptist, and what he admires about his aunt is intricately connected to her being Baptist. He sees his best hope of being like her in trying to also be a good Baptist. If he says only, “I am Baptist because my aunt is a Baptist and she is a good person,” there are many reasonable rejoinders: good people can have false beliefs, perhaps the aunt is a good person for reasons unconnected to her being Baptist, lots of people are good without being Baptist. However, if he goes on to explain how she goes about being Baptist, in what ways he wants to be like her, how it seems that the Baptist faith helps him to be like her, he uses lots more than his share of air time. The unspoken constraint in philosophy for children discussions is that reasons need to be brief, and counter-examples need to be brief. Otherwise, the requirement of equal access cannot be met. But if one knows that one’s full reason for some conviction involves quite a long story, and a story that contains features quite peculiar to one’s own experience, one may not be helped to individuality by locating oneself within a community of inquiry. One does not promote autonomy by telling someone: you may entertain any belief that you can explain and defend briefly in terms that other children will understand.

The situation is worse for a child who believes that God told her something. How should a child make other children understand that her world includes an extra person whose promptings she does not feel entitled to ignore? If the child feels a call to a committed, celibate religious life, what possibility is there for the child to locate her decision in relation to the decisions of other children? (In the 1960s, about 25% of the graduates of a St. Paul, Minnesota girls school entered  the religious novitiate; this is not a fanciful case.)

Of course, for the sanity and safety of children, one hopes that they inhabit a world in which they have enough in common with other children that they can develop shared concepts through the community of inquiry and can find their place in relationship to others. As Ann says, “Each child in the community, in his or her own way is trying to make sense of the world. Further, it is a great burden to expect children to do this on their own.” (192) But we must allow for the possibility that children may sometimes have to make sense of the world on their own because the presuppositions and conditions of the community of inquiry do not allow them to adequately express or defend their convictions.

I think this point applies to more than just religious views, though the problem comes up most remarkably with those. Lots of convictions in human life are rooted in long stories of relationships and observed lives. One says: “I want to be like my father” or “I’ll do anything to avoid turning out like my father,” and there’s a story behind that: a story that could be told, only not in a classroom with 20 children all needing a chance to talk within an hour’s class time.

Why not say something important but modest about philosophy for children: it is a way of thinking through some important concepts, to help children come to know themselves through their relationships to others? This is one important way that they come to know themselves and to develop their autonomy.  It is a particularly useful way, because it enables communities to maintain practices that contribute to everyone’s welfare: friendship, fairness, loyalty.

Thirty years ago, when I was working actively at a local elementary school, I took on an intern to conduct some extra sessions. I gave him strict instructions to stick to the stories provided and to observe the ritual of philosophy for children discussion. I learned later that he had taken it upon himself to challenge directly the religious convictions of students in a way that endangered both my program in the school and the careers of those who had supported me. At that point, it was enough to tell him that he had made a bad strategic mistake. But I wanted to say more: he had made also a philosophic mistake. This sort of position cannot be addressed by simply raising objections and considering arguments pro and con. A whole different approach is needed.

That was also brought home to me, somewhat later, when I interviewed an intelligent and charismatic spiritual healer from Australia. During the interview, she explained that part of her own journey was to return to her aboriginal community of origin after a western education and to make contact with the ancestors and spirit guides, some thousands of years old. In passing, she added, “Only five or six of them come with me for most speaking engagements, but when I come to America, all twenty want to come along.” I realized that, for her, the room contained twenty more people than I could see, and the fact that I could not see them did not, for her, count against the claim that they were present. We moved on, in the interview.

It was natural for Ann Sharp, in the early years of her work with philosophy for children, to want it to solve the full range of educational problems, to address the needs of the world for mature and intelligent leadership. As I consider ways of scaling back the claims that Sharp makes for this practice, I am brought up short when I remember that, in my own community, children are being recruited as suicide bombers, children are being lured into cults, children are developing idiosyncratic mythologies that move them toward terrifying destructive acts. Without some forum for discussing what people care about most, what people are willing to give their lives for, I don’t see any way to help such children. At the same time, I cannot share Sharp’s optimism that the standard practices of philosophy for children, the customary classroom ritual, will bring about a transcultural consciousness, an ability to place one’s own commitments within the human community of diverse commitments. One might hope that the habits of reflective evaluation, developed through weekly philosophic conversations on relatively safe matters of common concern, will be internalized in the way children talk to themselves about matters they may not be willing or able to share in public. Surely, philosophy provides better support for those facing religious decisions and crises (the young Muslim considering joining ISIS, for example) than most of what happens in elementary and secondary schools. At the same time, it seems clear to me that some substantial new experiments are needed to find ways of respectfully addressing the deeper concerns and convictions of children.

In the article “Silence and Speech in Pixie,” (Studies in Philosophy for Children: Pixie, 1996), Sharp comes close to addressing this point. She also shows how the novel Pixie  implicitly makes space for a kind of individual development that does not take place through conversation or through the individual locating himself or herself in relationship to others. Pixie contains a very talkative girl, the title character, and a boy, Brian, who does not speak until the end of the story. Ann’s article is a long list of the possible reasons why someone might choose not to speak. As one might expect, some of these identify deficiencies or harms, conditions that need to be corrected: the child has never been listened to, has been oppressed. A working community of inquiry can draw a child with these deficiencies into the common world and the common conversation. Ann suggests that Brian may simply use other modes of communication besides speech to enter into the dialogue. He may simply be a non-standard member of the community of inquiry. But Ann also lists some other possibilities, not fully fleshed out, but enticing: his silence may be a religious response to the world, akin to that of Christian monks, a silence growing out of a sense of language as an inadequate response to the world. She also considers the idea of silence as conscience, as a state of being so attentive to the world that there is no room for speech.

These possibilities suggest a limit to the claims for community of inquiry as the source of autonomy and the place where meaning is discovered. It seems to me important to develop these suggestions, to come to a broader view of education within which the community of inquiry is one important element in education for meaning making and for autonomy, suitable for many children with respect to many  aspects of their lives, but not a universal path to fulfillment. This opens up the possibility of seeking out partners in other pedagogical movements, to gradually realize the potential of democratic education, of education aimed at individual autonomy, across the full spectrum of human concern.

Eulogy for Ardes Shea, Who Died on May 24, 2016


My mother wanted to fly. She took all the classes she could in flying, facing down the college dean and a mean, chauvinist flight instructor. When the war  broke out, she wanted to join the Wasps. They said, “How long will it take you to gain ten pounds?” She said, “About a lifetime.” She did other things.

What did she want, when she wanted to fly? I think I know, because of a fine statement from the first person to fly, Wilbur Wright, “More than anything else the sensation is one of perfect peace mingled with an excitement that strains every nerve to the utmost, if you can conceive of such a combination.” She could conceive of that combination: peace and excitement. She wanted both of those, together. She just had to find them some other places than in the air. And she had to constantly fight for her right to be as big and intelligent and active as she was. Being small didn’t help.

There were things in her life she might not have chosen. She always missed the mountain behind the ranch, felt exposed on flat land. She enjoyed working in political organizations, and there wasn’t perhaps enough running room for that. She took every class and workshop she could find, but the range of her options was limited. So she did the best she could, finding ways to work behind the scenes to improve religious education, helping to found new groups and revitalizing existing ones.

She had tremendous energy. We keep finding quilts, large-scale star quilts with radical color schemes. The area of land she cultivated with, essentially, a hoe, was astonishing. Remembering her own favorite childhood memories, she tried to always have something good-smelling ready just when we came home from school. She also made vegetables so interesting that the meat sometimes got lost on the supper table. When she realized that baby trees need shade, she planted four-o-clocks by about 1500 of them, producing one year a farm field of flowers in brilliant colors, opening each afternoon.

She was always fielding surprise jobs. When my dad went off to teach in the fall, she suddenly realized that she was the one to milk the cows. She’d never done that. She had a toddler to watch. The cows outweighed her by a factor 5 or 6. One year, a new pig didn’t thrive, and she had a house-pig for the winter.  It turns out, pigs want as much attention as kids. The year I was away in Germany for Christmas, my sister was pretty sad, so she and Pat embarked on a huge project of making all the ornaments for the tree. There must have been more than a hundred of them. 

In her later years, she kept saying: I don’t get anything done. You had to have seen her in her prime to realize where that lament came from.

My mother left a good record of what she thought and felt. The Litchfield Area Adult Writers Group provided an ongoing, decades-long opportunity for her and Jim to reflect on their lives, monthly, ten months of the year. Her stories, preserved in the Writers Group annual collections and in her own book, It’s Classified, will keep the memory of her life and insights alive for those who are interested, as will her many stories told informally and in college story circles. She didn’t want to be anonymous, and she wasn’t. Bill Peltier takes her story, “Home for Christmas,” around to nursing homes. It will last a while.

In the last months, she barked whenever anyone mentioned her age. She thought, probably rightly, that such mentions were a prelude to statements like, “You’ve had such a nice, long life” or “Maybe it is time for you to go” or (unsaid) “Are you still around?” Her line was: “I have lots of things I want to do.” Of course, there were immediate things, such as anybody with a terminal illness might do: seeing the grandchildren, getting the place in order, publishing her book. But her things to do went  beyond that, beyond any lifespan people have yet achieved. She left some pretty interesting unfinished business. The things she wanted weren’t abstract, like “world peace” or “food enough for all.” They were concrete, doable, and big: she wanted every organization to go in a circle, first thing, so that everybody’s voice was heard. She wanted homework to make sense and to be about home, about practical problems in kids’ lives. She wanted kids to be asked for their opinions and listened to. She wanted home-makers to receive salaries, so that their work would be valued. And she wanted a lot more trees planted, to stop erosion and noise and snow drifting and wind.

She made a good start. The home place is now a garden plot within a nature preserve, with animals and birds I never saw in the 60s, attracted by the cover of her new forest. (Please, people don’t hunt there – except raccoons. She hated raccoons.)  By coming every spring to a residential college philosophy course, she made sure that the stories of her life got heard, and she communicated to the kids that their stories were important. She argued that the Forest City Stockade Festival should be hands-on education, not just entertainment,  and that kids should get in free. (Note to Festival organizers: if you start charging kids, she’ll haunt you.) She spent a lot of time, during her years selling vegetables and also later, just listening to people, and thinking about their stories. (I was always amazed that it took an hour to sell fifty cents worth of beans.)  Also, as perhaps the most visible tribute to her influence: if you drive on Highway 24 toward Litchfield, you will see the only coherent set of shelterbelts – rows of trees to stop wind – that I have seen in Minnesota. Carl Jensen said her trees would never grow, but he helped her plant them anyway. When they grew, he was converted, and lined his fields with rows of trees.

There’s obviously a lot more to do, to make all the eyes and ears and feet and hands in this society know their own strength, to help everybody reach out for both excitement and peace, for dignity and a life that makes sense. What she did was to stay alert, all her life and right up to the end (I was there), and to try as hard as she could to make what she cared about real. I’ll close with the ending of a William Stafford poem she knew:

For it is important that awake people be awake,
or a breaking line may discourage them back to sleep;
the signals we give--yes or no, or maybe--
should be clear: the darkness around us is deep.

She stayed awake. Her signals were clear. Now it’s our turn.