Thursday, February 26, 2015

Philosophy for Children and Residential Education

I spend time with two different democratic education practices: Philosophy for Children, a style of non-directive teaching developed by Matthew Lipman and Ann Sharp through the Institute for the Advancement of Philosophy for Children; and folkschool education, a kind of residential education begun in this country by Myles Horton of the Highlander Center in Tennessee and   adapted to U.S. undergraduates by John Wallace, who was for many years the convener of the  instructional team for a University of Minnesota course, "Lives Worth Living: Questions of Self, Vocation, and Community." I tried, in this 2004 paper, to say something about how these two  approaches to empowering students as independent thinkers are related.


Philosophy for Children and Learning Circles: How Do We Help People to Want to Be Better? Peter Shea -- June 24, 2008

"A sower went out to sow his seed; and as he sowed, some fell along the path, and was trodden under foot, and the birds of the air devoured it. And some fell on the rock; and as it grew up, it withered away, because it had no moisture. And some fell among thorns; and the thorns grew with it and choked it.  And some fell into good soil and grew, and yielded a hundredfold."  -- Jesus

Rich was worried yesterday about how to get people to want to be good, to want to want to adopt the policies that reason determines to just or generous or courageous. Clearly, some people do want to be good, and their good will makes rich and complex community possible. But how does any sort of instruction lure the agnostic, the undecided into making (and remaking, every day) this most basic commitment. Surely philosophy for children and other democratic education strategies have something to offer here, in two ways: they make the rich activity of a working, complex, decent community attractive to people, and they allow people access to the lives of others, so that everyone can see how it is possible for them to live, learning from whichever available models are appropriate to their particular stage of moral and psychological development. That’s the problem: it must be clear that rich, decent community is valuable and that it is possible for me, at my place in growth and development, to enter such community as a valued, competent participant.  In the paper that follows, I want to imagine in some detail philosophy for children and residential philosophy education based on story circles as two parallel strategies for helping people to want to be good, for making it likely that the seeds of moral and wisdom teaching fall on good ground and remain safe from birds and weeds. I then want to think a bit about what these two different traditions can learn from each other.

“Only Superman need apply” – the Demands of Teaching in the Spirit of Dewey

Think about what Dewey requires, in Experience and Education. Dewey thinks the right sort of teacher in the right sort of school must be familiar with the present experience of each student, the attitudes and impulses pressing forward into the future. That teacher is then responsible to craft experiences that move each student forward in a natural and continuous way, without big jumps, in the direction of growth and learning and wider sensibility – while somehow keeping a classroom of students together as a group. Given the real experiential and developmental diversity within any ordinary classroom, Dewey’s ideal requires superhuman powers in the educator; he or she must craft a group experience that connects seamlessly to the different particular experiences of each group member. The group experience must convince each student of the power of common, shared, cooperative activity while providing just the individual next step needed for his or her growth.

I want to think about philosophy for children and the residential story circle work I have been doing with a University of Minnesota team for the last few years as two related ways of approximating this ideal indirectly. Lacking the power to micro-manage individual growth, doubting sometimes that even God could figure that puzzle out, we who have developed these approaches have generated instead -- a blood stream: a changing nutrient stream of ideas and lives from which students are encouraged to take what they need. We cannot connect to the exact developmental status of each student; we can create an environment in which it is very likely that such connections will be made. And we can in the process show people (ourselves included) how much people can matter to each other, when they appreciate each other’s strengths and cooperate in ways that make good use of those strengths.

Philosophy for children makes participants’ minds (and to a limited extent, their life experience) available to each other, so that all come to depend on each other’s strengths of mind to help them understand something that they want to understand, and adapt what they need from the models represented in the group to promote their own growth. The community of inquiry arises because participants own the conversation; it progresses through careful coaching in listening and in knitting conversation together.

Residential Education in Philosophy and the Story Circle Approach

Like philosophy for children practice, a residential course in philosophy gives people access to each other’s minds and lives, in a safe environment, as a common treasure and as resources for each person’s development.

For the last ten years, a group of faculty, staff, and graduate students loosely affiliated with the University of Minnesota Philosophy Department has experimented with residential offerings, exploring notions central to the construction of a meaningful life. We began with weekend workshops, and then transferred what we had learned to a four week undergraduate course: “Lives Worth Living: Questions of Self, Vocation, and Community,” also known as Philosophy Camp. In our last offering, the eighth, we had 15 students; the staff included 5 instructors, 2 apprentice instructors, and a course grandmother. Two resident fellows took part each week and were available to students for conversation.

The principal activity of the course is a story circle, held most mornings after breakfast. The story circle strategy is adapted from traditions of the Highlander Folkschool in Tennessee. Students are asked to tell a story from their own lives concerning a topic or question that connects to the theme of the course. Stories are told without interruption. Students are free to pass; no one is pressured to tell a story. Large group discussion of the stories told is minimal – maybe 20 minutes at the end of the circle time. The primary processing of material from the story circles happens in spontaneous conversations later, during the mostly free afternoon and evening time.

A second circle activity structures our daily routine: the morning acknowledgement circle. Each person in the group is invited to say something about how other members of the group have contributed to his or her learning or growth or happiness in the previous day. This circle is also an occasion for people to say something about how things are for them, to mention anything they wish everyone to know. The same rules apply to these circles as to story circles. I was initially doubtful about the value of this activity, but students take to it with great enthusiasm, and I have come to think that it is a very important component of the work of the course, perhaps because it assures people in unmistakable ways that their contribution to the community is noticed and valued.

The leadership of this course is unusual. The leaders do not present a plan for the orderly processing of ideas and insights. Rather, they set up the structure of the time together, to make certain kinds of interactions likely, and they make themselves available, as participants in the process of reflection – telling their own stories, participating in group activities, and engaging in casual conversation. Although leaders make very light use of their power to direct the action, the leadership is a substantial presence: 9 people in a group of 23 had some leadership role. The work done by the leaders is subtle and diffuse. Partly, the leaders maintain faith in the integrity and power of the storytelling and discussion process; partly, they watch what is happening and adjust questions and course structures – time constraints, activities, general rules – to encourage deeper and more productive interaction and to avoid problems.

One example of such structuring is the allocation of time. All of our residential events, even weekend events, contain substantial stretches of unstructured time. There are breaks in the afternoon for naps and walks, and there are long evenings without programming. Perhaps most important, the groups prepare their own meals: all workshops and courses are conducted without cooks or housekeeping support. Meal preparation and housekeeping provide occasions for people to come together in new configurations around practical tasks.

The residential model requires a big staff, and that staff does, overtly at least, very little. The normal work of teaching, the normal structures of control and guidance and information, even in the minimal sense that philosophy for children requires, are mostly absent. The course is very similar to: a group of people getting together to talk and eat, like a family reunion or an Elks club meeting – but – with a few different rules, a different intention, and some very light supervision.

How do we understand the role that the story circles play in promoting thinking and discussion and growth within this residential community? Think of the way we learn from novels. Like novelists, the organizers of residential philosophy gatherings bring people together and invite them to learn from each other. Novelists exercise a different kind of control that over their “events:” some of the people they “invite,” their characters, are carefully chosen, and the way those people show themselves is carefully structured. The novelist leads the reader, a visitor to this temporary community, to particular insights and attitudes. The leadership of our residential education experiments is generally much looser, the selection of participants is much less intentional, and our goals are more general. Nevertheless, the educational environment of a novel is close enough to what we are up to in residential philosophy education to make the comparison and contrast worth exploring.

Discussing Jane Austen’s novels,[1] Alice Crary shows one way that an author can present a view – what Gilbert Ryle calls the “wine tasting” method. On this account, Austen introduces the reader to a variety of characters that exemplify a particular human quality – pride or susceptibility to influence, for example. The reader is invited to respond to these different characters – comes to see some as excessive, others as striking the right balance. By engaging the reader’s emotions in this complex way, Austen’s works persuade the reader how to stand with respect to important human problems. Novels provide a means of moral formation and initiation.

The story circle experience parallels this kind of learning. People tell their own stories around some important moral theme: standing up for what one believes, friendship, home. Like the novel, the story circle establishes a set of examples for important qualities through the stories told in the group. It may happen that – like Austen’s ideal reader -- people in the group take some of the stories told in the circle to display excesses or deficiencies or ‘striking the right balance;’ they may respond as, on Crary’s account, Jane Austen invites her readers to respond. However, people in the circle may also take the stories as simply presenting alternatives, as portraying different responses to significantly different circumstances.  The discussion does not necessarily move toward a moral result, as Crary suggests that Austen’s novels move toward an outcome, a recommendation: “be like the balanced heroine we see at the end of the novel.”[2] People have choices about how to take the stories that they hear.

A residential course that incorporates story circles is  close to  “normal” adult life – with differences. More material is generated in a residential course than in most adult living contexts, the course’s rules of engagement provide more opportunities for processing and following up than do the rules of normal adult living, and a group of thoughtful people watches over the whole process.

A residential course that makes story circles central to its practice is thus a half-way house beyond the classroom. Other kinds of teaching bring concepts, models, and thinking strategies into play in people’s consciousness, making them part of their repertoire. These concepts, models, and strategies are only useful if they help people in making sense of messy and unpredictable social circumstances – and if people actually use them in those circumstances.  The residential course introduces just the sort of complexity that adult life serves up. The framework of the course – the customs and procedures and rules – is constructed to help people learn from that complexity. Residential courses provide some practice at thoughtful life under very favorable conditions, to give students a taste for such life and to help them address the practical problem of making a place for life-shaping thought and conversation within their lives.

What can we learn from residential education for philosophy for children practice?

Philosophy for children is located between traditional education and Philosophy Camp. It fits within conventional classroom structures, without big staffs or special arrangements. Its materials are generally less directive of student attention than conventional novels or texts, allowing for individual choice and expression, and yet there is a content agenda behind each curriculum: the manuals say what we expect students to learn. Philosophy for children discussion leaders are committed to making participants fully available or accessible to each other, in one central dimension, at least: argument and conceptual thought. Lives and experience come into the discussion in an important but secondary way.

The continuation of discussion and cooperation, its integration into life, is just a hope on the horizon of philosophy for children practice. We can’t make it happen, or even set up the conditions under which it is likely to happen.  We can only hope that we have planted good seeds: as the parable of the sower suggests, the rest depends on the soil, the birds, the weeds, the water supply. Philosophy Camp tries to briefly produce the favorable conditions for the growth of “community of inquiry” into true and lasting community.

Philosophy Camp happens each summer because of considerable sacrifices on the part of instructors, and because we have devised some very creative financing. It is not a burden on the University; the last session of the course returned $10,000 to the U of M after expenses. I think this kind of program could be done at other institutions, using some of the experience we have gained from our experiments. However, one must admit that it will be impossible to do this at many institutions; the requirements of faculty good will and administrative support are simply too great. So what can be learned from this experiment for use in those contexts within which philosophy for children is traditionally done, in college and in elementary and secondary schools?

  1. Philosophy Camp makes clear where philosophy for children is heading, what sort of society it aspires to create. That’s important information for teachers, teacher trainers, and administrators. Perhaps the investment in this kind of program is justified, as part of outreach and of teacher training, if not in the central philosophy for children program.
  2. Philosophy Camp probes the relationship between “communities of inquiry” and the kinds of community that students encounter in their lives. Storytelling is closer to normal practice than philosophy for children discussions, and thus easier to insinuate into ordinary community practice. Our work defines an important task: to develop bridging strategies for making the ideals of the community of inquiry real in day to day life, for continuing and expanding Dewey’s project.
  3. The story circle is legitimate philosophic inquiry in a mode parallel to the logical and conceptual investigations that are the strength of philosophy for children practice. There is every reason to bring philosophy for children into the residential experience, as another mode of community building and shared exploration, and to bring the story circle into philosophy for children sessions. We have in fact made some use of philosophy for children strategies in our workshops and courses, and are in the beginning stages of figuring out how the two ways of teaching work together. The same work, from the philosophy for children side, would, I think, be very fruitful. In particular, it would bring some new people into the conversation.
  4. Within the constraints of the elementary school environment, or the undergraduate college environment, it must surely be possible to develop opportunities for those who have learned to work together in the community of inquiry to extend their sense of common purpose, of community life, to open their lives more fully to each other in other ways. We have found for example that the experience of preparing meals together is central to achieving our goals; people get to know each other in those contexts in ways that complement their interaction in the classroom. Why can’t we press these limits, and see how much more is possible?

One last point: both of these ideas taken together are not enough. The students who finished Philosophy Camp last week are now in withdrawal; the relationships back home are no longer satisfactory, and they don’t know how to fix them. Myles Horton, founder of Highlander, took it as his task to create “islands of decency.” That’s also what philosophy for children does. But human beings need and deserve continents of decency. To accomplish this, anybody who takes Dewey seriously has to worry about helping people establish in their lives: ground to stand on, communities that nourish, incidental conversations that have life and promise. We must ransack the full experience of democratic education, therapy, social work for tools to complete the work we have started, to make good on our promises.


[1]     Alice Crary. “Does the Study of Literature Belong Within Moral Philosophy? Reflections in the Light of Ryle’s Thought.” Philosophical Investigations 23:4 (2000): 315-350.

[2] One might think of the wine-tasting method as supplemented by the Three Bears method: the heroine overdoes, then underdoes, then gets it right. That sort of moral instruction happens in journey novels of various sorts.
 

No comments:

Post a Comment