Thursday, February 26, 2015

Plato on the Choice of a College Major

I teach Plato in ethics classes; I ask students to write about their lives, in the same classes. This forces the issue: can one, without twisting things around, bring Plato's thinking into dialogue with the concerns of U.S. undergrads in the 21st Century. I think this is an important question, because I think people come to undergraduate philosophy classes with some hope that they will be of use. I don't think teachers should change the subject until they have exhausted the search for a way to really be of use. This paper, presented for the Minnesota Ancient Philosophy Circle, is one effort to explore connections.


Friday, May 4, 2012
Plato and the Undecided Student: Deciding What To Think About

Peter Shea

Growing up, Socrates was my hero. I saw him as a guy who would think hard about whatever came up, making everyday experience interesting and deep. He wasn’t afraid to keep on thinking, when huge difficulties emerged – to live with uncertainty and doubt; he had no need to bring every discussion to some simple and satisfying conclusion. Also, he was willing to move around, taking on friendship, beauty, fighting in armor, mathematical knowledge.  He didn’t let himself get stuck on some one, intractable problem.

When I went to college, I majored in philosophy because, to me, that meant not majoring in anything at all: holding on to my universal hunting license.

Two new influences led me to write this essay. My students have made it clear to me that the choice of a major is a very big deal for them, morally and practically. It just won’t do for me as a teacher to have nothing to offer them with respect to what they see as the biggest decision of their college careers.

Martha Farah, a neuro-ethicist, came to speak at the Gustavus Nobel conference. Her closing remarks provided my most recent incentive to write about the choice of things to think about. She said:

“If we all we are is physical stuff, what the heck does anything matter? I mean, do I care whether one leaf blows east or west, outside on that lawn? No. So why should I care if you or I happens to get run over by a truck. What does anything matter? How do you find meaning in a physical world? Steven Weinberg, who is a physicist, wrote about this and said, ‘The more the universe seems comprehensible, the more it also seems pointless.’ And I think that, if that’s a problem for physical science, it is even more of a problem in neuroscience… Even if I am thinking my neuroscience thoughts and viewing it all as a physical system and at some level it doesn’t matter, the second I step back into my normal human being mode, I do think things matter.”
 
It was an odd moment. Farah realized that she was in front of an audience that had taken pains to come to this conference, and that she had just told them it was all meaningless.  Stepping firmly back into her human shoes, she ended her talk with a heartfelt testimony about how meaningful this conference had been to her.

Her speech reminded me of the physicists at Los Alamos, waiting for the first nuclear explosion, aware of arguments that such an explosion would ignite the atmosphere and end life on earth. I wanted to say to them, “Shouldn’t you at least wait a bit, to do an experiment that might put an end to physics in the entire universe?” In as similar way, I was tempted to ask Farah, “Shouldn’t you back off from lines of investigation that make investigation seem pointless? Isn’t this self-defeating scholarship?” Her remarks seemed relevant both to my choice of research projects and to my students’ choices of courses and majors.

The point of this paper is to ask what help might be found in Plato’s dialogues for thinking about what to think about and what to avoid. A related question is this: what openings are present in the Platonic canon, which is the staple of introductory philosophy courses, for initiating discussions about choices of major, choices of courses, and choices of intellectual “projects?”

What would Plato say to the college student trying to choose a major? Are there any areas of study that Platonic arguments picture as dangerous or self-defeating?
Consider this advice from the Apology, “"…the greatest good for a man [is] to discuss virtue [excellence] every day and those other things about which you hear me conversing and testing myself and others, for the unexamined life is not worth living for men…" 38a

That might argue for a philosophy major, with an ethics emphasis.   In Laches, mediocre offspring of great men are considering how to educate their own children, so that those children may surpass them and restore the family honor. 
The parents are trying to decide whether lessons in “fighting in armor” are worthwhile, and they consult three advisors famous for  battlefield accomplishments, two generals – Laches and Nicias – and Socrates, who is famous for his courage as a soldier.  The generals give conflicting advice derived from their understanding of the realities of battle. Socrates suggests that understanding any such matters depends on first understanding courage, and launches a long, twisty definitional discussion.

What strikes me about this, thinking as a parent who has made all sorts of similar calls about educational opportunities, is how bizarre this move is. All of the assembled discussants agree that winning battles is important. The relevant considerations for deciding about lessons are the “battlefield” appropriate considerations: does this training make someone an effective soldier. The overarching discussion of courage may be relevant to these ground-level decisions in some way, but such decisions can’t wait on the outcome of debates at the higher level. That’s like saying that questions about how to cook steak wait on the outcome of debates about vegetarianism. Surely, if the vegetarians make their case, that will at least diminish the interest of any reasonable person in cooking meat, but cooking classes can’t wait on the outcome of animal rights discussions. As the conversation moves further and further from practical matters, one can imagine the fathers sinking into despair.

One wants to ask: does Plato expect the reader to accept this odd substitution and hijacking of the debate? Is that the point of the Laches? I suspect not, though I am very far from a full account. I am impressed, first of all, by the care expended on Laches’ and Nicias’ practical speeches. The generals are shown as resourceful arguers, approaching the problem of an innovation in training with intelligence and insight. It is difficult to take the point of the dialogue to be that those arguments just don’t matter.

I think that Plato is playing a trick on the reader of the Laches. He is getting that reader to empathize with the parents, to doubt the relevance of philosophy, and then, in a very subtle way, making a modest point about the usefulness of philosophic education – as valuable for Laches and Nicias and also for the young boys.

The reader’s anxiety, as the dialogue progresses, comes from the inconclusiveness and abstractness of the discussion: how will this discussion ever lead back to “fighting in armor” or any other concrete teaching question? But does the discussion need to reach some conclusion, to be useful? Suppose one remembers, as any informed Athenian would remember, the disasters that befell Laches and Nicias later on. Laches failed to recognize the value of strategic retreat, and failed to stand up to the demands of his soldiers for action: he marched his army out of safe cover to confront a superior force, when reinforcements were on the way. Nicias failed to effectively stand up to his fellow citizens, in opposing the Syracuse campaign and the impossible team selected to lead it. Both, in other words, imagined courage in too a narrow way: as consisting of standard successful moves on the battlefield. 

I take Plato to be saying something like this, in the Laches: “I freely admit that philosophic discussions can go on a long time without reaching a resolution, and also that they are sometimes quite distant from practical concerns. But suppose that Laches and Nicias, in their early years, had been invited to take even the first steps on the philosophic path, to notice that their central virtue, their reason for living, was broader and more diverse than they had thought, encompassing many behaviors, in different circumstances, and involving relations not just with enemies but with fellow citizens. The first steps of Socrates’ investigation take them already beyond the mistakes that cost them their lives. ” On this view, Laches is a defense of a little philosophy – of the power of even simple lines of investigation to shake people out of dangerous assumptions. It suggests, concretely, that the boys need a philosophy tutor. (Perhaps the Laches is part of the recruiting campaign for the Academy.)
So Laches supports at least the idea that one should minor in philosophy, whatever one’s major. The first steps of philosophic progress are valuable, even to practical people.

Is there an argument in the dialogues for majoring in philosophy? I think there might be one in the Theaetetus, but it is a limited argument. Theaetetus begins with the story of a young man coming home, dying, having fought well. It then flashes back to show Theaetutus as a boy, a very promising mathematics student whose estate has been mismanaged and wasted by his trustees. There’s an odd interlude at 10e5 where Socrates mistakenly claims that Theodorus, a mathematician and Theaetetus’ teacher, is the trustee of Protagoras’ estate. Theodorus corrects him: “It’s not I but rather Callias, the son of Hipponicus, who’s the trustee in charge of Protagoras’ things. I turned away a bit too soon from bare argument to geometry.” Callias is notorious for wasteful expenditure: Protagoras and Theaetetus are both badly served by their trustees. 

What does this move in the dialogue mean? One possibility occurs to me: the dialogue is criticizing Theodorus for turning from bare argument to geometry – for switching his major from philosophy to mathematics, leaving an important “estate” to the care of a supremely careless man. What is the estate: the whole question of the possibility of knowledge as opposed to opinion, of investigation as different from persuasion. The objections that Protagoras raised needed an answer, for public reasons: in the absence of some public ideal of truth, people will come to regard debate as simply a persuasion contest. The sorts of foolish and wasteful military campaigns in which good young men are killed result from a debased intellectual climate. Theodorus stands convicted of betraying Protagoras, and Athens, and, ultimately, men like Theaetetus, all for not persisting in his philosophy major. (It is important that the young Theaetetus meets Socrates, who could initiate him into philosophy, shortly before Socrates’ death. The responsibility for training Theaetetus falls to Theodorus, who can only teach him mathematics. The line of philosophic transmission forward from Protagoras and Socrates is broken.)

If this reading is right, the dialogue argues for a particular major – but only for a particular sort of person. Theodorus is talented; he could have helped to unravel the problems raised by Protagoras. He could have continued and passed on the tradition of philosophic inquiry. There was an important public reason to do so: Athens needed a sound epistemology as it confronted the problems of democratic government. Theodorus had the responsibility to take on the important problem of his time, and he did not rise to the occasion.
This is a promising suggestion, for the undecided student. One’s choice of a major is not just a personal choice: one should think about what one can contribute to the world and about the particular needs of the world into which one becomes an adult.

Are there any majors that Plato rejects? There is the unargued claim in Republic that the desire to look at corpses is a base appetite contrary to reason (which might keep people out of mortuary science and forensic medicine). There is also an argument in Republic against teaching dialectic to young people that may contain the germ of a more general rejection. At 538c, Plato pictures a young man who has grown up respecting certain guidelines of action, without having thought about them very hard. This young man has immoderate desires, which he restrains out of respect for the principles he has learned. Then someone questions him about his beliefs and “reduces him to the belief that this thing is no more beautiful than it is ugly, and the same with what is just and good and the things he honored most.” This person will then give way to his desires, since he no longer respects the guidelines that have held them in check, and will descend thereby into what Plato elsewhere describes as a kind of madness. Only carefully selected people who have been through rigorous training can, at the age of thirty, be trained in dialectic and trusted to use it to find the truth. In particular, at that age, they can be trusted to keep at the search for the requisite five years, and not wander off skylarking after they finish day one of the “chastity” unit: “arguments against.”

A philosophy major is not safe for the sanity of most students – and perhaps other majors, like anthropology and sociology, are dangerous in the same way: they validate ways of life different from the one that maintains the young person’s sanity. Like the Theaetetus recommendation, this advice is particular: to students of a certain age, whose principles are not well established.

This comes close to Farah’s suggestion that certain lines of thought leave one with the sense that nothing matters. Plato here argues that moral dialectic is one such line of thought, at least for those under the age of thirty.

Finally, we come to the closest point of contact between Plato and Farah, Socrates’ autobiographical remarks in Phaedo about his reasons for turning away from the natural sciences, in particular anatomy and physiology. Two passages seem to me to sum up his reasons. The first responds to, specifically, an account of his remaining in prison in terms of some causal story involving his bones and muscles, “These bones and sinews would long since have been off in Megara or Boeotia, impelled by their judgment of what was best, had I not thought it more just and honourable not to escape and run away, but to submit to whatever penalty the city might impose.” 99a

The point  seems to be that causal accounts of the kind one could hope for from natural science would explain some human behavior, but not behavior like “remaining in prison to face execution when one has the option of fleeing to comfortable exile in Megara.” This would be a pretty straightforward argument: natural science cannot explain the most interesting phenomena – in fact, it predicts the opposite of what sometimes happens. (This seems to be actually a problem for neuro-ethics: the accounts of the evolution of sacrificial behavior work far better for limited sacrifice, like that involved in child raising or food sharing, than for martyrdom on principle.)

There’s an interesting feature of this example: the action that is inexplicable (remaining to face execution) is the product of a sophisticated train of thought, the fruit of a lifetime of philosophic reflection. If Socrates had pursued physical science, this counter-example might well not have existed. The decision to seek accounts other than physical causes for action brought about the behavior that physical causes cannot explain.

The Phaedo’s second objection to the pursuit of natural science accounts of human action seems to be this: “To call these things the reasons for my actions, rather than my choice of what is best, and that too though I act with intelligence, would be a thoroughly loose way of talking.” 99b
So what is wrong with loose ways of talking? Surely, whatever accounts the neuroscientist gives of the course of a human life are going to be different from accounts given in ordinary terms. Someone diagnosed with Obsessive Compulsive Disorder might say: “I wanted to be sure whether I had turned off the stove. Each time I left the house, I couldn’t quite be sure I had turned it off, so I returned to the kitchen again and again.” The neuroscientist Norman Doidge, describing the brain states involved,  writes, “Because the caudate didn’t shift the gear automatically, the orbital frontal cortex and the cingulate continued to fire off their signals, increasing the mistake feeling and the anxiety.” It turns out that, in this case, when people describe their obsession in the looser way suggested by brain imaging, this description enables them to take control of the process and end the compulsive episode. (They say, “That’s my OCD kicking in” and shift their thinking away from the problem ‘Did I turn off the stove?’ to some distracting and pleasant memory.)

Perhaps what Socrates is saying here is just that some phenomena, like people acting for the best, are so interesting that any investigative method that obscures such phenomena is unacceptable. Or he might be saying that the normal ways of talking about the interesting phenomena like the choice of the best, are good enough and do not need to be supplemented. Or perhaps he just doesn’t have access to examples in which natural science accounts are illuminating, in the way that the neuroscience account of obsessive behavior is both illuminating and helpful in therapy, so he doesn’t see what use there could ever be for a looser account of human action.

It is not clear how close the objections in the Phaedo come to Farah’s worry, that complete accounts will lead to a sense that nothing matters. One can take Socrates to be saying that some kinds of accounts are just inadequate to moral facts, like choice of the best, or that they are useless for a discussion of such facts. But that is different from saying that one will cease to think that anything matters if one studies natural science. There is, however, this possible link: to the extent that one attends to those phenomena that natural science explains best, one may come to forget about moral choice, perhaps also to forget to make moral choices. And that may be equivalent to: coming to think that nothing matters. Socrates the natural scientist might have no reason to attend to moral thinking, and might not live the sort of life that provides a difficulty for natural scientific accounts.

I want to conclude by saying something about the ethics of teaching. It seems important that teachers of philosophy validate the intellectual problems confronted by students, encouraging them to respond to arguments within the tradition. In my experience, the most pressing decisions undergraduate students face are decisions about what to think about: what courses to take, what majors to pursue, what careers to enter. It is important that philosophy teachers identify points of access to the introductory canon, points at which those works address student concerns. This paper is one preliminary contribution to that project. 










No comments:

Post a Comment